MODELLING PROCESSES IN A FRACTAL
NETWORK:
A POSSIBLE SUBSTRUCTURE FOR CONSCIOUSNESS.
Richard Dryden
16 January 1996
Abstract: It is proposed
that consciousness does not emerge from a single level of
biological organization (for example: from computational
activity at the synaptic level in networks of neurons), but is a
consequence of interdependent modelling activities by networks
at different levels of organization including the molecular,
organelle, and cellular levels, in some way entrained to produce
consciousness. Fractal stacking and intercommunication of
networks at different levels is proposed as a substrate that may
be required for consciousness, either natural or machine-based.
Adoption of this conceptual starting point may overcome some of
the difficulties encountered when reductionist strategies are
applied to the study of
consciousness.
Introduction
Contemporary discussions of consciousness tend to
draw upon the most deeply held features of our individual
world-views, be it quantum theory, information theory, chaos theory,
parapsychology, or spiritualism, in the hope that some combination
of these will provide enlightenment. There is clearly a problem of
self-reference here in that consciousness is both the tool and the
object (Miller, 1962):
consciousness is trying to understand itself, and
has no reserve of modelling capacity to aid simplification or to
step back and view itself from a more sophisticated metasystem. If
we try to model consciousness by making simplifying assumptions or
using reductive methodologies, it is in danger of slipping away in
the process - consciousness seems to be a product of ‘wholeness’
rather than 'partness'. However, that is not to say that any attempt
to understand consciousness is without merit or that progress cannot
be made - there are sufficient regularities in the observable
universe to allow us to extrapolate from things we can know more
readily to those which are less accessible, such as
consciousness.
In the proposal that follows, I shall combine ideas
from general systems theory and neural network theory to prepare a
conceptual framework from which to view consciousness. Essentially,
I shall suggest that consciousness does not emerge from activities
at a single level of biological organization (for example: from
computational activity at the level of synaptic interconnection in
networks of neurons), but is a consequence of interdependent
modelling activities by networks at different levels of
organization, in some way intermittently entrained to produce
consciousness.
General systems theory
I have found the ideas incorporated into general
systems theory (GST) very helpful in developing an understanding of
the biological realm. GST identifies recurring patterns of
organization in systems of different types. There are several
variants of this theory, but I shall take the concepts developed by
Bertalanfly (1968) as a starting point. Central to GST is the
concept of partially-bounded open systems interacting with their
environments by way of inputs and outputs, as illustrated in Fig. la. A
selected part of the environment 'flows through' an open system over
time, being changed by it - 'transformed' - in the process. Although
some system boundaries have an observable reality, for example: the
outer membrane of a cell, we must also appreciate the role of an
observer in 'drawing' boundaries: this separation of our world into
systems is still a reductionist approach.
Open systems are made of interdependent parts, each
of which can be thought of as an open system in its own right. Open
systems at a given level of organization can interact with each
other to produce systems that 'emerge' at the next higher level of
organization: for example, atoms and molecules interact to form
cells, cells interact to form multicellular organisms, and the
organisms of some species interact to form societies. Within a given
level of organization, there can be recognizable patterns of
interaction such as hierarchy.
For me, the strength of GST lies in the recognition
of patterns that recur in systems at different levels, and I find it
provides a framework for incorporating reductionist scientific
observations into a more holistic worldview. For this reason, I feel
that GST can contribute to the debate about
consciousness.
From my studies of embryos and other biological
systems, I would add another feature to this generalized conception
of an open system: a capacity for the system to 'model' its
environment in some way. That is, over a period of time the system
develops a changing representation of its environment through its
two-way interactions and as a consequence of its internal
organization and functions.
I have chosen the word 'model' for this discussion
in the belief that it has a more neutral feel to it than the more
commonly-used alternatives such as 'consciousness' and 'awareness'
(see Velmans, 1995, for a discussion of the difficulties in using
these latter terms). No attempt will be made to pin down the exact
meaning of 'model' at this stage; rather, it will be used to stand
for representational activities in general, sentient or otherwise.
Therefore, at the human level, 'model' would include both conscious
and subconscious activities. For the sake of simplicity, I have
placed the 'model' within the boundary of the open system in Fig. la (‘m’)
- this is not necessarily to imply a physical presence within the
system, simply a close interrelationship between modelling
activities and the other systemic structures and processes at that
level of organization.
Although at the human level conscious experience
gives us direct access to modelling processes, the suggestion that
we should extend the idea of modelling capacities to systems at
other levels may appear particularly speculative. However, evidence
in support of this view is beginning to accumulate, and recently
there have been several publications proposing that cells,
organelles, and even molecules have the capacity for computational
and representational processes as a consequence of their
organization (eg: Albrecht-Buehler, 1985; Hameroff, 1994; Bray,
1995).
This suggestion that open systems in general,
regardless of level, might possess a faculty for modelling echoes
panpsychism - the idea that all matter contains some quality that
may be called 'mind' or 'consciousness'. Panpsychism has often been
classified along with vitalism as being both unscientific and
unnecessary (see for example Popper and Eccles, 1990), although
panexperientialism and panpsychism have recently reappeared as
discussion topics (de Quincey, 1994; Seager, 1995). However, it will
be suggested below that modelling can be achieved by processes
familiar to contemporary science, specifically those occurring in
natural and artificial neural networks, and do not require that we
formulate additional properties of matter. This is not to say that
the experiential aspect of consciousness will necessarily
emerge from the modelling processes being proposed here - rather
that we need a suitable conceptual framework from which to begin to
tackle the ‘hard question' of consciousness delineated by Chalmers
(1995).
An internal model would impart a degree of autonomy
to a system over its environment, or at least that would be the
impression given to an observer, since stimulus-response loops will
be buffered and modified by the computational activities of the
model. The result will be that the system's responses show variation
over time: the response elicited by a particular input pattern may
not be the same when the same input is tried again after the system
has gained other experiences in the interim. De Quincey (1994)
summarises it like this: "A 'compound individual' is a hierarchical
society of suborganisms each of which has its own level of
experience and capacity for self-determination (for instance, an
animal compounded of living cells, or a cell composed of organic
molecules)" (page 223).
If this is the case, it allows the possibility for
more subtle behaviour of individual systems as they interact with
their environments and each other. In the case of a developing
embryo, we can envisage the growing community of cells forming a
network of social interactions (Dryden, 1991), each cell
continuously harmonizing its intrinsic drives and gene selection
with the environmental cues impinging upon it. At the same time, the
embryo as a whole seems to have an identity or model, since
perturbations to the normal flow of development can be coped with
and responded to, even though particular cells are lost or damaged.
Thus, when open systems interact socially, it seems that a new
potential for creativity is produced.
Limitation of GST
There is, however, a shortcoming in this way of
looking at the world and the systems within it. The stratification
of the observed world by GST into levels of organization seems
innocuous enough in the sense that it recognizes the apparent
‘wholeness' of a molecule, cell, or person, and identifies repeating
patterns at each level, but the problem then arises of understanding
how events at one level impinge upon events at another - for
example, do events at a higher level determine what happens at lower
levels (‘top-down' causation), or do events at lower levels dictate
what happens at higher levels ('bottom-up' causation)? Or can both
occur? Interestingly, scientific disciplines seem to be stratified
in a similar way, each focusing on a particular level of
organization, and a similar problem arises: a discipline that works
well within one level (eg: cytology) may not have an obvious
explanatory value for a discipline at the next level 'up' (eg:
psychology). It is as if we have a good ‘within level' science but
have need of a better 'between level' science (interscience?) to
link the levels. Given that we consider the universe to be an
interconnected whole, and science to be a consistent methodology for
learning about it, this is quite surprising, and gives us cause to
re-examine the way we observe the world and make subdivisions. Part
of our current difficulty in understanding consciousness may result
from inappropriate separations being made.
The problem of linkage also applies to the proposal
that models may exist in systems at different levels: how would
those models interact? (See Fig. 1 b.) For
example, how would models within cells possibly interact with or in
some other way contribute to consciousness at the human level? In
the context of panpsychism, Seager (1995) calls this the
'combination problem': "how the myriad elements of 'atomic
consciousness' can be combined into a new, complex and rich
consciousness such as we possess" (page 280). Reductionism is an
approach which requires dismantling a system and studying its parts,
or studying the behaviour of a system in an artificially simplified
and controlled environment. However, consciousness appears to be a
property emerging from an intact system, from ‘wholeness' rather
than 'partness', and may not be reducible in a conventional sense
without risking losing the very insight being sought.
Neural networks
Although GST stumbles at this point, it is possible
to make progress with the idea of interacting models at different
levels by bringing in and modifying the concept of neural
networks.
The term 'neural network' is rather loosely used and
may refer either to a network of biological neurons forming part of
a nervous system (natural neural network) or a computer
simulation of a network composed of interconnected units with
neuron-like properties (artificial neural network). In both
cases, each node in the network has one or several inputs of
variable 'strength' (usually both excitatory and inhibitory) and
summates the inputs, giving rise to an output or outputs when a
stimulus threshold is crossed. (For a review of neural networks and
a discussion of some of their limitations, see Crick,
1989.)
Artificial neural networks are often simulated with
three layers of units: an input layer, an intermediate 'hidden'
layer, and an output layer (Fig. 1 c,
lower diagram). The connections between units are changed during
periods of 'training' or 'learning': connections that contribute
towards correct behaviour become strengthened, while connections
that contribute to aberrant behaviour are given less weight, with
the result that a distributed 'memory' of the task is established
across the network in the pattern of different-strength connections.
A trained network contains information about associations,
categories, and algorithms in its pattern of connection strengths
and operational rules, and in the sense used above, therefore
embodies a 'model' of its task.
The neural network concept provides an explanation
for modelling capacities in networks of interconnected units, and is
playing a significant role in developing our understanding of
biological systems. As noted above, the concept can be applied not
only to studies of neuronal assemblies, but also to individual cells
and parts of cells such as organelles and macromolecules
(Albrecht-Buehler, 1985; Hameroff, 1994; Bray, 1995).
Combining GST and the neural network
concept
The 'units' which form the nodes of a given network
share most if not all of the properties already delineated for open
systems: inputs, some kind of inner transformation or function,
outputs, and interactions with other units. Therefore, we can redraw
a neural network with open systems as the units (Fig. 1c, upper
diagram).
But by building on our experience with GST, we can
take the analysis further. If we are considering a natural neural
network, the units are the neurons. Each neuron is a complex and
living assemblage of interacting parts, and those parts can also be
viewed as open systems. So we could model the neuron itself as a
network with, for example, its organelles forming the units.
Similarly, we could model organelles such as the mitochondria as
networks, with their constituent molecules forming the units. This
process of identifying network characteristics could probably be
extended further to include molecules such as proteins which are
known to respond to environmental cues. We begin to see an
interconnected pattern of networks within networks. This
interpretation is summarised in Fig.
2.
Looked at in this way, biological organization
appears as nested sets of networks, with the units in a network at
one level being networks in their own right at the next level down,
and the units at that lower level are also formed from networks, and
so on. A suitable term for this arrangement would be fractal
network, since it captures the quality of self-similarity or
recurring patterns at different levels (ie: nets-within-nets). The
term 'fractal' is being used here in a slightly different way from
Merrill and Port (1991) and Globus (1992), who describe fractal
network patterns while considering a single level of organization
rather than linking different levels, although clearly these two
uses of the term 'fractal' are complementary. Hameroff (1994) also
hinted at the pattern of organization outlined above: "the
cytoskeleton within each of the brain's neurons could be viewed as a
'fractal-like' subdimension in a hierarchy of adaptive networks"
(page 114).
Discussion
Consciousness is widely believed to be the result of
physiological processes in the brain: the 'stream of consciousness'
perhaps being a product of changing patterns of nerve impulses
flowing through an incredibly complex network of neurons
communicating by way of synapses. By this view, consciousness
'emerges' from computational brain activities at the
neuronal-synaptic level. However, not everyone is convinced that
this approach will ever provide a sufficient explanation of
consciousness, particularly its experiential aspects. As Hameroff
(1994) points out: "the mechanism of consciousness may depend on an
understanding of the organization of adaptive ('cognitive')
functions within living cells" (page 97). Others propose the
need for intervention by non-computational processes (Globus, 1992;
Penrose, 1994), or even the introduction of novel properties of
matter or information at a fundamental level of scientific
description (Chalmers, 1995; Seager, 1995).
If we are to take into account the levels of
organization that underpin the synaptic level of brain activity, we
need some effective way of linking activities at the different
levels. In the hypothesis outlined above, the behaviour of an open
system at any given level of organization is considered to be the
result of social interactions between partly autonomous components
which are each capable of modelling aspects of their environments.
Modelling is considered to be a fundamental property of open
systems, allowing them to interact in subtle and creative ways. It
is suggested that the modelling and social activities at each level
are integrated to produce the emergent properties recognized at
higher levels, including consciousness.
Interaction, together with the presence of
individual capacities for modelling, can be a source of new
complexity in open systems. Structures, specializations, processes,
and institutions emerge in a way that presumably would not be
possible without interaction between individual members with social
potentials. Communities of cells build organisms; communities of
ants build complex anthills. In the human social context we are
familiar with systems of government, justice, education, health care
and so on which arise as emergent properties of individual social
interactions. If we form a conceptual link between these creative
activities of social systems and the adaptive behaviour of neural
networks, then we begin to have a better understanding of emergent
properties, including consciousness.
To bridge between levels, I have suggested that it
is helpful to integrate the open system concepts of GST with the
concept of neural networks, giving rise to a fractal arrangement of
adaptive nets. This approach has two advantages:
The fractal network concept provides the potential
for more 'depth' when discussing consciousness in the sense that it
links activities at more than one level of organization. However, by
simply adding more layers of networks we are not necessarily going
to feel much closer to answering the 'hard problem' of consciousness
(Chalmers, 1995: what is the source of the experiential aspect of
consciousness?), since doubts have been expressed about the ability
of monolevel networks to exhibit understanding of their
computational activities (eg: Searle, 1990), let alone have
subjective experiences.
Nonetheless, the interconnected nature of the
hypothesized fractal network may help us to understand how proposed
lower-level influences might interact with consciousness. For
example, there is considerable discussion about the possible
involvement of quantum coherence in consciousness. Penrose (1994)
suggests that "coherence could be part of what is needed for
consciousness" (page 408), and with Hameroff (1994) believes that
cytoplasmic microtubules might provide a suitable location for a
'dithering' between quantum and classical realms. Seager (1995)
agrees with Penrose that "only coherent multiparticle systems will
preserve the peculiar quantum mechanical properties that underlie
the appropriate 'summation rules"', and continues "only systems that
can maintain quantum coherence will permit 'psychic combination' so
that complex states of consciousness will be associated only with
such systems" (Page 285).
The fractal network concept appears to accommodate
the possibility of between-level coupling, but at this stage it is
not clear how this might be achieved or maintained. The concept has
the advantage that all parts of the network remain interconnected
and therefore represent a single entity, so although at the synaptic
level of brain function there may be shifting patterns of activity,
there could still be continuity and intercommunication in a more
global sense at sublevels, perhaps allowing extensive
coherence.
There is reason then to believe that conscious
experience requires some form of 'entrainment' or resonant coupling
of activities at different levels. Since conscious alertness cannot
be sustained continuously for long periods; and is punctuated by
periods of reduced alertness including sleep, this may be an
indication of a periodic need to uncouple activities at different
levels, perhaps to allow restorative processes to be carried out. In
the absence of coherence, it could be envisaged that computational
processes would still be possible within a given level, but perhaps
without the full experiential accompaniment.
Although speculative, the fractal network hypothesis
is open to testing by currently-available methods. Fractal networks
are amenable to computer simulation (Merrill and Port, 1991), giving
an insight into their computational properties. The effects of
blocking communication between networks at different levels of
organization could then be studied - this may illuminate the
suggestion that anaesthesia operates by blocking normal microtubular
action and thus uncoupling quantum coherence effects (Hameroff,
1994). It would also be interesting to test the suggestion that
modelling at the molecular and organelle levels influences the
modelling capabilities of individual cells: extrapolation from these
lower and less complex levels might help us to better understand the
emergence of human consciousness.
References
Albrecht-Buehler, G. (1985), 'Is cytoplasm
intelligent too?', Cell & Muscle Motility, 6,
pp. 1-21.
Bertalanffy, L.v. (1968), General systems theory
(New York: Braziller).
Bray, D. (1995), 'Protein molecules as computational
elements in living cells', Nature, 376, pp.
307-12.
Chalmers, D.J. (1995), 'Facing up to the problem of
consciousness', Journal of Consciousness Studies,
2(3), pp. 200-19.
Crick, F. (1989), 'The recent excitement about
neural networks', Nature, 337, pp.
129-32.
de Quincey, C. (1994), 'Consciousness all the way
down? An analysis of McGinn's critique of panexperientialism',
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1(2), pp.
217-29.
Dryden, R. (1980), 'Visualizing systems',
Kybernetes, 9, pp. 175-9.
Dryden, R. (1991), 'Networks of social interactions
between embryonic cells', In: Human Biology: an integrative
science, Proceedings of the Australasian Society for Human
Biology, Volume 4, pp. 1-9 (Nedlands, Western Australia: The
Centre for Human Biology).
Globus, G.G. (1992), 'Toward a noncomputational
cognitive neuroscience', Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience,
4(4), pp.299-310.
Hameroff, S.R. (1994), 'Quantum coherence in
microtubules: a neural basis for emergent consciousness?',
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1(1),
pp.91-118.
Merrill, J.W.L., and Port, R.F. (1991), 'Fractally
configured neural networks', Neural Networks, 4, pp.
53:60.
Miller, G. (1962), Psychology: the science of
mental life (New York: Harper & Row).
Pen rose, R. (1994), Shadows of the mind: a
search for the missing science of consciousness (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Popper, K.R., and Eccles, J.C. (1990), The self
and its brain (London: Routledge). Seager, W. (1995),
'Consciousness, information and panpsychism', Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 2(3), pp.272-88.
Searle, J.R. (1990), 'Is the brain's mind a computer
program?', Scientific American, 262(1),
pp.20-S.
Velmans, M. (1995), 'The relation of consciousness
to the material world', Journal of Consciousness Studies,
2(3), pp. 255-65.